User:Robbie McClintock/1964/The Philosophy of Culture

From A Place To Study
Jump to navigation Jump to search
The Philosophy of Culture:
A Study of Humanistic Pedagogy

1918 — 1939


A Prospectus by
Robert O. McClintock
of a Dissertation
to be Submitted
in Partial Fulfillment of
the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy

Introduction: The Outlook of Humanism

Humanism holds that the animal, man, makes himself human by using mind to order the universal flux that he finds both within and about him.

By thinking, men order nature and themselves; and the ordering thoughts are their

culture. As the anthropologists say, culture is a whole way of life; but, as the classicists say, culture, nevertheless, has a qualitative structures for Instance, forced to choose between preserving either the concept "cigarette" or "number," prudent men would select the latter. Thus, the philosophy of culture concerns the principles of selection that prudent men should apply to their whole cultural heritage in order to structure it for the optimum benefit of its holders.

Since neither God nor nature sponsor man's knowledge, culture is as insecure as the mortals who hold and form it; and this insecurity makes education the sole guarantor of the laws that men have given nature and themselves. The successive generations maintain and extend the world to the degree that each assimilates and develops the structured ideas which make the world intelligible. Unless men are trained to appreciate and improve the cultural means by which predecessors created their inner and outer environment, the continued existence of these orders will be endangered; and, although the future is always uncertain, insufficient cultural training will increase the probability of man’s destruction of his own creations.

Humanistic pedagogy tries to insure that each generation receives a cultural training adequate to maintain man a progressive self-liberation. The philosophy of culture establishes the goals of this pedagogy; and wherever culture is transmitted from the more mature to the less mature, humanists find a potential for educating men.

I propose to study how humanistic pedagogy developed during the inter-war years. During this time humanists perceived a cultural crisis caused by certain radical defects In the structure of valuations inherited from nineteenth century thought. Part I of the study will describe the humanistic interpretation of this cultural crisis that had been long developing and which the Great War made manifest. In a second movement, humanists re-examined the philosophy of culture In the light of twentieth century science and developed new principles of cultural selection which, they hoped, would give human life more stability, purpose, and potential. Thus, there were humanistic developments in physics, biology, psychology, and technical philosophy; and Max Scheler, Ernst Cassirer, John Dewey, Jacques Maritain, and José Ortega y Gasset led many others in applying a new philosophy of culture to the problems of humane living. These developments will be the subject of the second, longest Part of the dissertation. Lastly, humanists proposed and attempted various programs to transmit a more perfectly structured culture from the mature to the immature. In Part III I shall survey some of these efforts to actuate humanistic educational theory.

Taken together, I believe these three parts will constitute an incomplete, but substantial study of humanistic pedagogy during the liter-war years. Given the unsatisfactory — nay, nonexistent — literature on the subject, the proposed study should constitute a useful contribution to knowledge. What kind of contribution that might be, I try to indicate below with a more detailed outline of each chapter.

Part I: Humanistic Pedagogy in a Naturalistic World

At all tines the purposeful maintenance of the cultural heritage has been a basic activity of humanists. The ability to give purpose to the process depended on the philosophy of culture, which assigned different values to different ideas. During the nineteenth century the intellectual basis for this normative structuring of knowledge seemed to disappear when the biological, social, and psychological sciences overcame the distinction between a law for man and a law for thing. Rather than the sense of duty created by a philosophy of culture, the new social sciences confronted men with a sense of objectivity and inevitability. A vision of an objective, inevitable development was not one to evince the sublime in men. The naturalistic attitude derided concern for the spirit as an obsession with illusions, and proved its worth by providing ever better material conditions. However, some doubted whether men could live by bread alone; and, if they could not, what would happen to the ideological part of life when normative thinking had been decimated by the scientific attitude?

Moralists had long been calling for a transvaluation of all values in order to combat matter-of-fact naturalism. The Great War gave this call a ring of urgency. Humanists responded. Thecultural fatalism of Marxian and Darwinian materialism, the apparent undercutting of reason when the human sciences revealed the rationalizations, and a sense, nevertheless, of a potential for advance in the human soul, if only it could remain human: these provoked humanists to restate the permanent problem of maintaining culture through normative action in terms that were adequate for "their time." They agreed that unless men gave more care to the place of knowledge, reason, and value in the conduct of life, the continued self-liberation of the human spirit was doubtful.

Thus, in Part One I shall describe the humanistic statement of the crisis in culture during the inter-war years. The essay should show how humanists viewed nineteenth century cultural history, it should analyze what they feared in their own spiritual situation, and state what they felt was necessary to avoid the intellectual dangers confronting them. This last topic will lead into Part II, for it will introduce the two basic problems the philosophy of culture tried to solve: namely, to secure its intellectual moorlings by achieving scientific respectability without loosing its normative orientation, and then,to develop a convincing, normative structure for the culture that would better minister to human needs.

At this stage, a fairly complete bibliographical listing will indicate more of my intentions than would the fabrication of an elaborate outline; and so the reader who is satisfied with the above exposition and is curious about the likely contents of Part II, may feel free to skip the concatenation of books below: (* = important)

Irving Babbitt
Rousseau and Romanticism (1919)
Democracy and Leadership (1924)
Joseph Wood Krutch
Our Changing Morals (1925)
The Modern Temper (1929)*
Walter Lippmann
Liberty and The News (1920)
Public Opinion (1922)*
The Phantom Public (1925)
American Inquisitors(1928)
A Preface to Morals (1929)*
John Dewey
Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920)*
Human Nature and Conduct (1922)
The Public and Its Problems (1927)*
Individualism Old and New(1929)
John Cowper Powys
The Meaning of Culture (1929)
Frank K. Notch
King Mob; a study of the present-day mind (1930)
T.S. Eliot
Selected Essays (1935)
After Strange Gods (1934)*
Wyndham Lewis
Time and Western Man (1927)
F.R. Leavis
Mass Society and Minority Culture (1930)
Culture and Environment (1933)
José Ortega y Gasset
The Modern Theme (1923)*
The Revolt of the Masses (1930)**
Essays in Obras completas
Jacques Maritain
Théonas, ou, Les entretiens d'un sage et de deux philosophes sur diverses matières inégalement actuelles (1921)
Rétlexions sur l'intelligence (1924)
Paul Valéry
Discours de réception à l'Académie française (1927)
Regardes sur le Monde Actuel (1931)
Varieté, premier volume (1931)
Julien Banda
La trahison des clercs (1927)*
Discours à la nation européenne (1933)
Albert Schweitzer
The Philosophy of Civilization (1923)*
Max Scheler
Krieg und Aufbau (1916)
On the Eternal in Man (1921)*
Schriften zur Soziologie und Waltanschauungslehre, 4t. (1924)*
Karl Jaspers
Man in the Modern Age (1931)
Nicholas Berdyaev
The end of our time (1933)
The fate of man in the modern world (1935)

Any suggestions as to grievous omissions or unwarranted inclusions on this list, will be appreciated. In the essay I shall not attempt to shew that each of these men were humanists, but will synthesize from their writings something of an ideal type denoted “the humanist statement of the cultural crisis.” Exposition of the thought of particular humanisms will be left to Part II in which the contributions of Dewey, Ortega, Maritain, Cassirer,, and Scheler will again become relevant.

Part II: The Philosophy of Culture: 1918-1939

As the previous Part will show, humanists feared that when evolutionary thinkers successfully treated man as the object of natural science, they vitiated normative thought. With respect to the question of what should be done with the cultural heritage, it appeared that those who wished to renounce most of it as prescientific fancies had a dangerously strong argument. Certainly a critical philosophy of culture could not flourish until it Justified its place in a scientific era; yet to many it was clear that such a flourishing philosophy was needed.

Science, itself, provided the basis for a re-invigorated philosophy of culture. The weakness of humanism had been its incompatibility with the evolutionary sciences which showed that man was at the mercy of nature’s shaping forces. Important movements in twentieth century science demonstrated the opposite relationships: man’s mind shaping the linage of nature on the basis of which he could act. The more alert humanists were quick to take up developments such as relativity physics, vitalistic biology, and gestalt psychology, and to use them to strengthen the foundations of the philosophy of culture. In technical philosophy the movement of phenomenology altered the conception of “fact" in a way which made it ouch more difficult to argue that aoae methods were primly scientific and others slothfully were not, the first three chapters of this Part will show how these developments helped create an intellectual mood conducive to philosophizing about culture.

In the remainder of Part II I shall discuss some major contributions to the philosophy of culture. How Max Scheler applied the phenomenological method to ethics, philosophical anthropology, and the sociology of knowledge shall be the subject of the last half of chapter 3. The remaining chapters will concern four philosophies of culture in which individual thinkers attempted to structure the cultural heritage on the basis of the way each thought man gave order to the world. Thus, Ernst Cassirer studied culture in the light of his conception of man as the maker of symbols, as distinct from animals who merely could recognize signs. John Dewey contended that in discriminating between aspects of culture, we should recognize that man, uniquely, constructs experiences in order to judge rationally the potentials open to him. Jacques Maritain maintained that in structuring culture we should remember that man is the being capable of recognizing certain universals, in the light of which he can assign all things their proper place. Lastly, Ortega asserted that man was the being who theorized in order to act more effectively; and culture, therefore, should be organized to maximize man’s opportunity to develop theories about nature's processes and to construct ideals for his own aspirations. All four applied their systems to politics, art, science, history, and philosophy; and although their theories differed, they were not contradictory; and thus, their principles were complimentary, not conflicting, contributions to the philosophy of culture.d

1. The Human Laws of Speculative Physics

Disagreement still dominates assessments of the significance of relativity and indeterminacy for philosophy. Nevertheless, it is clear that these developments were amenable to the humanistic interpretation that both physicists and philosophers made. In this chapter I shall describe how physical theorists accentuated the role of the knower in knowing, how they showed that the laws of nature were the laws men gave to nature, and proved that there were certain limitations on man’s power to give intelligibility to things. Then I shall recount how physicists and philosophers used these arguments as important features in the renascent epistemology of humanism.

Fortunately, a literature suitable for this chapter has developed. The technical papers concerning relativity and indeterminacy, are not particularly relevant to recounting the humanistic interpretation of these developments,, (although they are very relevant to the eventual determination of the validity of the interpretation; but that is a determination I do not propose to attempt). Again, I would appreciate critical comments on my proposed bibliography.

Max Planck
A Survey of Physical Theory(1922)*
Das Weltbild der neuen Physik (1929)*
Where is Science Going? (1932)
The Philosophy of Physics (1936)*
Determinus oder Indeterminus? (1938)
Wege zur physicaklischen Erkenntnis (1944)*
Albert Einstein
The Meaning of Relativity (1921)
Sidelights of Relativity (1922)
Mein Weltbild (1934)
P.A. Schilpp, ed.Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (1944)
Edwin Schrödinger
Über Indeterminus in der Physik (1932)
Science and the Human Temperament (1935)*
Science and Hummanism: Physics in Our Time (1951)*
Werner Heisenbergberg
Wandlungen in der Grundlagen der Naturwissenschaft (1935)
Physics and Philosophy (1958)*
The Physicist’s Conception of Nature (1958)
Max Born
Experiment and Theory In Physics (1943)*
Natural Philosophy of Cause and Chance (1948)*
Continuity, Determinism and Reality (1955)*
Sir James Jeans
Physics and Philosophy (1943)*
Arthur S. Eddington
The Nature of the Physical World (1929)
New Pathways in Science (1935)
The Philosophy of Physical Science (1938)
Ernst Cassirer
Substance and Function (1910)
Einstein’s Theory of Relativity (1921)
Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (1936)
F. S. C. Northop
Science and First Principles (1931)
The Logic of the Sciences and the Humanities (1947)
C. Lanezoe
"Albert Einstein and the Role of Theory In Contemporary Physics," American Scientist, 47: 41-59 (1959)
Gilbert Ryle
The Concept of Mind (1949)*
L.S. Stebbing
Philosophy and the Physicists (1957)*
Stephan Toulmin
The Philosophy of Science (1953)
Foresight and Understanding (1961)*
Adolph Grünbaum
Philosophical Problems of Space and Time (1964)

Some background reading In Charles S. Peirce, Ernst Mach, and Henri Poincare will be necessary.

2. The Value of Gesalt

Vitalistic biology and gestalt paychology also proved congenial to the humanistic temper. In the former it was shown that the vital capacities of the animal entered into the structuring of its “environment" (the world as it can perceive it); and this led directly to ethics, for man was the only animal with vital capacities for moral action. Ignoring these in considering the human environment would pervert the scientific attitude. Gestalt psychology also showed how the perceiver structured the world. This initiative made him responsible for its proper configuration. In this chapter I shall describe these developments, stressing their humanistic contributions to ethics, epistemology, and value theory.

This chapter will be based on the following bibliography:

Baron von Uexküll
Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere (1909)
Theoretical biology (1926)
Hans Driesch
The history & theory of vitalism (1914)
The crisis in psychology (1925)
Der Mensch und die Welt (1928)
Ethical principles in theory and practice (1930)
Max Wertheimer
Drei Abhandlungen zur Gestalttheorie (1925)
Productive Thinking (1945)
Kurt Koffka
Beiträge zur psychologie der gestalt (1919)
The growth of the mind (1921)
Principles of gestalt psychology (1935)
Wolfgang Köhler
The Mentality of Apes (1921)
Gestalt psychology (1929)
The place of value in a world of facts (1938)*
Dynamics in Psychology (1940)

This chapter will be shorter than the first; and it might be advisable to reverse their position, for the effect of physical theory on humanism occurred mainly through epistemology, which is also the subject of the third chapter. But tho content of this chapter may lack the dramatic stature that an opening chapter on relativity and indeterminacy could give to the philosophy of culture.

3. Man’s Ideas of Phenomena

During tho late nineteenth century, Franz Brentano, an Austrian psychologist, led a philosophical school concerned with value theory. Because the impact of the "Austrian theory of value" was delayed until the twentieth century and because it was a prelude to the phenomenology of Husserl and Scheler, this chapter will begin by describing this theory and how it gave rise to phenomenology. The central part of the chapter will deal with Husserl’s conception of the phenomenological method, its significance for the philosophy of science, and its re-establishment of idealism in philosophy. In the last 1926)part of this chapter I shall follow Max Scheler’s imaginative applications of this outlook to questions of ethics, philosophical anthropology, and the sociology of knowledge. His work was cut short by an early death; but, nevertheless, it constitutes one of the major contributions to the philosophy of culture during the inter-war years.

Proposed Bibliography:

Franz Brentano
Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (1874)
Wahrheit und evidenz (1930)
Christian von Ehrenfels
System der werttheorie (1898)
Alexius Meinong
Psychologisch-ethische untersuchungen zur werththeorie (1894)
Über Annahmen (1902)
Zur Grundlegung der allgemeinen Werththeorie (1923)
Edmund Husserl
Logische Untersuchungen (1901)
Ideas: general introduction to pure phenomenology (1913)
Cartesian meditations: an introduction to phenomenology (1931)
Husserliana gesammelte Werke
Philosophical essays in memory of Edmund Husserl (1940)
Max Scheler
Der Formalismus in der ethik und die Materiale wertethik (1913)
Abhandlungen und Aufsätze (1915)
On the Etdernal in Man (1921)
The nature of sympathy (1923)
Schriften zur Soziologie und Weltanschauungslehre (1924)
Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft (1926)
Man's place in nature (1927)
Philosophical perspectives (1929)
Karl Mannheim
Ideology and Utopia (1940)

There is a Collected Edition of Scheler's works which 1 hope to be able to use.

4. Neo-Kantianism and Ernst Cassirer

The Marburg school of neo- Kantianism contributed much to the philosophy of culture. Its elder leaders wore Hermann Cohen and Paul Natrop, who influenced such leading humanists of the inter-war years as Heinrich Rickert, Arthur Liebert, Ernst Cassirer, and José Ortega y Gasset in the first part of this chapter I shall discuss the contribution of neo- Kantianism to humanistic cultural thought. Ernst Cassirer transcended the Kantian interest of the Marburg school by his work on the problem of knowledge and symbolization. His system was based on a conception of man as the maker of symbols and within this system he dealt with almost all facets of culture. In the main part of this chapter I shall examine Cassirer’s contribution to the philosophy of culture, trying to show how he structured the intellectual heritage in a useful way for humanistic pedagogy.

Proposed bibliography:

Paul Natrop
Sozialpädagogik (1899)
Platos Ideenlehre; eine Einführung in den Idealismus (1903)
Gesammelte Abhandlungen zur Sozialpädagogik (1907)
Vorlesungen über praktische philosophie (1925)
Heinrich Rickert
Die Grenzen der naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbilding (1902)
Kulturwissenschaft und naturwissenchaft (1921)
Kant als philosoph der modernen kultur (1924)
Die Logik des Prädikats und das Problem der Ontologie (1930)
Grundprobleme der philosophie, methodologie, ontologie, anthropologie (1934)
Arthur Liebert
Geist und Welt der Dialektik (1921)
Erkenntnistheorie (1932)
Philosophie des Unterrichtes (1935)
Die Krise des Idealismus (1935)
Der universale Humanismus (1946)
Ernst Cassirer
See Bibliographies in
Schilpp,ed., The Philosophy of Ernst Cassirer (1949)
Klibansky and Paton, eds., Philosophy and history ; essays presented to Ernst Cassirer (1936)

I Intend to study Cassirer's major works and to follow special problems through his work.

5. Kant, Pragmatism, and John Dewey

One of my purposes in this dissertation is to try to treat Dewey in the humanistic realm of discourse that arose in the twentieth century. Although we may agree with Santayana that Dewey had a metaphysics, we should ask whether it was naturalistic. The term “experience" is the key to whether Dewey was a naturalistic or humanistic metaphysician. If we understand "experience" in a sensationalist, post-Lockean, positivistic sense, in which the world writes upon our blank slates, Dewey will appear as a naturalist. But, if we understand "experience" in a post-Kantian sense, in which the experiencer formulates the experience, Dewey will appear as a humanist. Dewey began his philosophical career as a neo-Kantian and he became a "primatist," the founders of which, Pierce and James, were anti-positivistic and influenced by Kant.

If a humanistic interpretation of Dewey proves viable, a new reading of his educational thought will be possible. It will show Dewey's educational concern becoming progressively more inclusive and cultural: starting with the child and the school, he turned to democracy and education; and, after careful studies of politics, science, art, culture, and valuation, he returned to education under the heading of "the problems of men and the present state of philosophy.” In this interpretation, Dewey’s pre-war studies of education will be secondary to his post-war studies of culture and philosophy.

Proposed bibliography;

C.S. Peirce
Chance, love, and logic: philosophical essays (1923)
Values in a universe of chance; selected writings of Charles S. Peirce (1958)
William James
The Principias of Psychology 1890
Talks to teachers on psychology & to students on some of life's ideals (1892)
The Will to Believe (1896)
Pragmatism (1907)
The varieties of religious experience (1902)
John Dewey
See bibliography in
Schilpp, ed. The Philosophy of John Dewey (1939)

I will stress Dewey's writings from Democracy and Education on, whloh was as much a prelude as It was a culmination. I also want to see how much of his post-war thinking was foreshadowsed in his early essays for The Journal of Speculative Philosophy.

6. Jacques Maritain and Christian Humanism

Maritain is important to humanistic educational thought because he has arrived at generally the same conclusions about culture as other humanists, but via neo-Thomism rather than Neo-Kantianism. This different grounding raises a problem, for Maritain frequently criticized other humanists because he disagreed with their premises. Perhaps when I achieve a better acquaintance with his work, I will find he does not fit into the subject. Be that as it may, I now think his different premises produce a view of man like that of many other humanists; and, if this is true, his many sided writing on culture and its relation to human life will contribute to my synthesis of humanistic pedagogy.

Like Scheler, Cassirer, Dewey, and Ortega, the man, Maritain, is of a depth of mind that sets him apart from any school; and so I do not intend to treat him within the confines of scholastic philosophy. I will stress the humanistic and the cultural in his writings, which stretch from 1914 to 1961, and will look for the principles by which ha thinks culture should be organized. As Maritain’s work since World War II appears to follow the lines he established earlier, I feel free to treat it as if it fell within my main pariod.

7. José Ortega y Gasset and the Examined Life

Ortegas early works referred mainly to problems of Spain, and I will deal with these only in so far as they illuminate his later, general philosophy of culture. From 1923 until his death Ortega devoted himself to advancing humanistic conceptions of art, history, society, and philosophy, and to strengthening the cultural institutions — the university, library, theater, and publishing -- which could make his conception operative in human life. I shall stress these contributions to a philosophy of culture, showing especially how his idea of man-as-theorizer enabled him to combine natural science and human duty in one system.

I have written a chapter length essay on Ortega to show how he attempted to make culture a more beneficial force in life by improving its quality and its dissemination. I was concerned mainly with his early and middle periods, and need to do some more reading in his late and posthumous writings, especially La idea de principio en Leibniz. The nine volumes of hie Obras completas are the basis of a bibliography which I can supplement with writings by his contemporaries and followers.


These seven chapters should show that humanists advanced a substantial philosophy of culture during the interwar years. They treated the major issues of the time in a way that enabled men to have a selective attitude about their efforts to transmit the heritage of ideas. Although in school practice the interwar years are remembered as a time of intellectual leveling, we will see that humanistic pedagogy went against this trend with respect to the school and the society at large. Humanists worked to discover bases for valid distinctions in the cultural heritage; and their revisions re-founded the traditional system of selection: the correct use of mind, the exercise of critical judgment, the pursuit of right reason. It was the capacity for this pursuit that humanists, as always, sought to maintain. They did so not only in word, but by deeds as well.

Part III: Toward Actuation

As a complement to Part One, I will write an essay describing some attempts to implement humanistic pedagogy. There ware widespread efforts to improve the university, especially to balance the trend towards specialization by establishing an institution responsible for the valid synthesis of available knowledge. Ortega wrote on this and founded the Instituto de Humanidades in 1947 to fulfill his theory. Max Scheler, Paul Valery, Julian Benda, F.R. Leavis, Irving Babbitt, and Karl Jaspers wrote about the university. There is, I know, a great deal more material, perhaps too much.

A second humanistic educational development may be found in the new ways the press and publishing were used. Several reviews, especially the Nouvelle Revue Française and the Revista de Occidente were founded as forums for a universal interest in culture: the indexes of the latter show articles on subjects from science through literature by authors from every part of the world. Critics, both popular and elite, flourished. On one hand Walter Lippmann proposed a fourth branch of government, and on the other, F.R. Leavis wrote a barbed secondary school text, Culture and Environmentt. John Dewey’s contributions to the New Republic should be noted. The scientists often misguided efforts to popularize their work went along these lines; and their mistakes have led to one of the new, synthetic disciplines in the university, the philosophy of science.

Another possibility would be an examination of the effect of the Bauhaus on modern architecture and design. I have not gone into this sufficiently to do more than mention it.

The purpose of Part III, whatever substance goes into it, will be to show that the highly developed educational theories described in the main part were not thoughts in a void: They made a difference in the way some men acted, and still should.

A Note on my intended Method:

If any of the chapters I have contemplated above are to succeed, they will have to be tightly organized about a theme. My intention, after considering the source material, is to decide what is the principal contribution of that material to the philosophy of culture, and then to write an essay advancing and defending my interpretation as completely and convincingly as I can. Since I have not arrived at my interpretations, there is no sense in trying to say how each essay will be organized. However, I have worked out the lengths in terms of which I shall think in writing each of the component essays: Introduction, 15 pages; Part I, 50; Ch. 1, 40; Ch. 2, 25; Chs., 3-7, 40 each; Part III, 50; and Conclusion, 20. These total approximately 400 typewritten pages.